- Two equivalent reduced real cubic forms are equal.
- A reduced real cubic form belonging to U is irreducible.
- Any irreducible real cubic form is equivalent to a unique reduced form.
(1) Let F andbe two reduced cubic forms and
such that
. Then
and since
and
are reduced, it follow from Lemma 5.2 that
and that M is an automorphism of
. We now have only a finite number of possibilities (exactly 16) to test for M. Let
.
First, if
, we have
hence the conditions a>0 on F and
imply M=I.
If P=R and
, we have
hence the conditions
on F and
imply a=|d|, hence the additional conditions |b|<|c| on F and
give a contradiction.
In the case P=R and Q=0 and
, then we have
, and the conditions
on F and
imply a=|d| and the additional conditions |b|<|c| also lead to a contradiction. Note that an easy calculation shows that in this case
.
If P=Q and
, we have
and hence the conditions |b|<|3a-b| on F and
give a contradiction.
If Q=0 and
, we have
and hence the conditions b>0 on F and
give a contradiction.
Finally assume that P=Q=R and M is one of the six matrices given by Lemma 5.2. Then an easy computation shows that F is of the form
. The reducedness of F is equivalent to a>0, |b|<|3a-b|. For the six matrices of Lemma 5.2, we have respectively
,
and
. The first two leads to a contradiction because of the condition |b|<|3a-b|, and the other four together with a>0 imply
, and the matrices
and
as automorphisms of F. Thus in this case, and only in this case, the automorphism group of F is nontrivial and is cyclic of order 3 generated by one of the above two matrices. This finishes the proof of (1).
(2) Let
be a reducible real cubic form. We will successively replace F by equivalent forms, which we will still denote
by abuse of notation, until we can conclude. Set
. Assume by contradiction that F is reducible. Then by transforming F by a suitable element of
we may assume that a=0 and hence
since
. By changing if necessary F into -F, we may assume that
. Changing
into
for a suitable k, we may assume that
and finally by changing if necessary
into
, we may assume
. We thus have
, and
.
Let p be an odd prime dividing b. Since
, we have
, but since
, by definition this means that
plus an additional condition. In particular, by Proposition 3.3 (2) we have
, hence
, so
, hence
, and this leads to a contradiction unless p=3 by Proposition 3.3 (3). But if p=3, we have a=0 hence
and
so Proposition 3.3 (4) implies that
, contradiction again.
There remains the case of p=2 dividing b. In that case we have
hence
, so
. Since
, we have
. We conclude as before by Proposition 3.3 (2) that
, hence
hence
, in contradiction with
coming from Proposition 3.3 (3).
We deduce from the different cases above that b=1, and hence c=0 or c=1. Hence if we call G the final cubic form that we have obtained, we have
for a certain
, and
with c=0 or 1. Hence
or
. Since these are reduced quadratic forms equivalent to
which is reduced, we have
. Now, since d<0 (otherwise
and
is impossible), the only automorphisms of
are
, and since we must have a>0, this implies M=I hence F=G, contradiction.
(3) The uniqueness statement follows from (1). Let
be an irreducible real cubic form and
its Hessian. By the usual theory of reduction of quadratic forms (with the added twist that matrices of determinant -1 are allowed), we can find
such that
is reduced, hence by changing F into
we may assume
reduced.
In all the cases of Definition 5.3, it is easily checked that the use of the 16 matrices of Lemma 5.2 will lead to a reduced form. Note that it is essential to assume F irreducible, otherwise the result would be false. More precisely, it is enough to check that the forms with a=0, or b=0 when Q=0, or |b|=|3a-b| when P=Q or a=|d| and |b|=|c| when P=R are all reducible. This finishes the proof of the proposition.